March 19, 2024

Privacy: A Personality, Not Property, Right

The European Court of Justice’s decision in Google v. Costeja González appears to compel search engines to remove links to certain impugned search results at the request of individual Europeans (and potentially others beyond Europe’s borders). What is more, Costeja may inadvertently and ironically have the effect of appointing American companies as private censors and arbiters of the European public interest.

Google and other private entities are therefore saddled incomprehensibly with the gargantuan task of determining how to “balance the need for transparency with the need to protect people’s identities,” and Costeja’s failure to provide adequate interpretive guidelines further leads to ad hoc approaches by these companies. In addition, transparency and accountability are notoriously difficult to cultivate when balancing delicate constitutional values, such as freedom of expression and privacy. Indeed, even the constitutional courts and policy makers who typically perform this balancing struggle with it—think of the controversy associated with so-called “judicial activism.” The difficulty skyrockets when the balancers are instead inexperienced and reticent corporate actors, who presumably lack the requisite public legitimacy for such matters, especially when dealing with foreign (non-U.S.) nationals.

The Costeja decision attempts to paper over the growing divergence between Anglo-American and continental approaches to privacy. Its poor results highlight internal normative contradictions within the continental tradition and illustrate the urgency of re-conceptualizing digital privacy in a more transystemically viable fashion.

Informational privacy must ultimately be re-theorized in a manner that would obviate—or at the very least palliate—the need for a stand-alone, ill-defined, and under-theorized “right to be forgotten.” That right is in essence a procedural one predicated on the impracticable idea that individuals “own” data, rather than a right to their identities themselves. It therefore fails to accord with the long-established (continental) tradition of personality rights, which, unlike its common law counterpart, emphasizes personhood not property. In the end, a more robust construction of privacy predicated on protecting identity would allow for a more nuanced balancing of privacy and freedom of expression.

Consequently, rather than further expanding an already divisive, property-based procedural “right to be forgotten,” Europeans (and perhaps others as well) would do better to harness the ample protections found in traditional, substantive civil concepts pertaining to privacy—most notably personality rights—so as to develop a coherent set of principles that contextualize identity and the perception of personal (and/or corporate) identity in the digital realm. For unlike the poorly theorized “right to be forgotten,” which unceremoniously imports all the rights traditionally associated with property, the civil tradition offers time-tested, flexible principles for this purpose.

Comments

  1. “All rights are property rights.” – Only right wingers posing as libertarians believe that nonsense. On the other hand, whatever harms companies like google is good.

  2. With an agreed mathematical formulation of the situation, a rational, reproducible solution is feasible. Without it, not so much.

  3. August Hurtel says

    All rights are property rights. The reason why this ‘right to be forgotten’ is poorly thought out is that after information is broadcast, the information shall now reside on other people’s property- i.e. servers, brains, various devices, etc…

    Many of these things will be owned by people who are neither the one wanting to be forgotten, nor the party who did the broadcasting. Any attempt to force such a ‘right’ would, in fact, result in the forced violation of many other people’s property rights.

    But, if we complicate matters by assuming there’s something more than property rights, then people can pretend that it is okay to violate other people’s property rights in favor of this differently derived right.

    The primary way to defend privacy is to prevent the initial distribution of private information- especially the sort insisted upon by governments.

    • Samson Corwell says

      “All rights are property rights.”

      That is certainly not true.

      “The reason why this ‘right to be forgotten’ is poorly thought out is that after information is broadcast, the information shall now reside on other people’s property- i.e. servers, brains, various devices, etc…”

      So?

      “Many of these things will be owned by people who are neither the one wanting to be forgotten, nor the party who did the broadcasting.”

      What’s your point?

      “Any attempt to force such a ‘right’ would, in fact, result in the forced violation of many other people’s property rights.”

      Begging the question. All rights are backed by force.

      “But, if we complicate matters by assuming there’s something more than property rights, then people can pretend that it is okay to violate other people’s property rights in favor of this differently derived right.”

      This is muddled. First off, it is you who is doing the assuming when you say all rights are property rights. That is a substantial claim that needs some seriously good argument(s) to back it up. Second, people don’t “pretend” anything here, as if they somehow really hold your views. They don’t think that any rights would be violated by enforcing their privacy rights. In fact, they think it is the property owners who are violating their rights.